Soothing
The Savage Beasti
One
of my wife's favorite compositions is “Symphonie
sur un chant montagnard français,”
(Symphony
on a French Mountain Air).
It was written in 1886 and was Vincent d'Indy's, best known work, his
Opus 25. Also known as the “Symphonie
cévencole,”
it was named after the Cévennes Mountains in southern France. The
chant
montagnard français is
a lovely melody, a folk song d'Indy heard while at Périer,
overlooking the mountains. The entire piece lasts just under thirty
minutes.
Just
about the same length is a work by another of her favorite composers,
Johannes Brahms. That work is his Opus 24, “Variations
and Fugue on a Theme by Handel,”
which he wrote a quarter of a century earlier. This particular
composition is considered by some to be one of the finest sets of
variations ever written.
What's
interesting about these two works is that both rely on a prior
musical idea.ii
Put otherwise – more starkly, perhaps – they represent a form of
plagiarism. In each case the theme used was very old – out of
copyright in current terminology – but, in a sense, these were
stolen ideas.iii
We don't view them that way, however it isn't clear to me why that's
the case. Perhaps it's the copyright itself – however that is
human law, and doesn't really tell us what is “right” and
“wrong.”iv
More and more we
read about authors who have appropriated, without attribution,
passages from other works. It's plagiarism as well, and, once
discovered, it's scorned by all. That's an easy one. In principle,
the distinction between that and a theme and variations seems less
clear though. If the use of “stolen” goods, and the benefit from
them, is “wrong,” what's the difference between these two
situations? It can't be the age of the stolen material.
The bigger question
– the one that governs this and numerous other issues – relates
to the ethics of benefiting from any crime. Perhaps the other end of
the spectrum that begins with variations on a folk song is the use of
information that the Nazis gained during their infamous experiments.
While current research facilities use ethics committees to help
investigators avoid going off track, ethics was not a consideration
for the Nazis. But are we justified in ignoring the results of their
work, criminal as it might have been, if it can help someone now?
How is the use of that information different from the transplanting
of organs harvested from someone murdered in a robbery?v
There is a concept
in law which deals with the “fruit of the poisoned tree.” If
information is obtained in a forbidden manner, anything derived from
it is also illegal and inadmissible for use in a prosecution. Law
enforcement, therefore, cannot benefit from the crime of gathering
intelligence illegally. They won't be able to use it in court. And
if leads were obtained from it, they'll be off limits as well. But a
similar question is whether we should we listen to the
“whistle-blower” who has pledged confidentiality to his employer.
In reality the two situations have something in common. Both use
nominally protected information. In both cases, notwithstanding any
self-serving justifications, an individual tried to benefit from
questionably gathered knowledge.
And
there are numerous other examples of the same problem – the
benefiting from a proscribed action. Can you torture one person to
prevent harm to another?vi
Can you monitor “free speech” in order to gather information
about planned crimes? What are the ethics of spying? Of “sting”
operations? Is it justified to offer a reward or a bounty, since
this will wind up with someone benefiting from the fact that a crime
was committed? Is the lawyer who defends the criminal benefiting
from the crime? Can the lawyer – or the criminal for that matter –
gain by telling the story of the crime? And if the criminal has
stolen something but has been found “not guilty,”vii
is he entitled to keep the booty?
What do you do
about situations in which you're willing to reward the criminal?
Gilad Shalit, a kidnap victim, was returned to Israel at the cost of
over a thousand Palestinians who had had been convicted of committing
crimes. An individual or a company may be willing to pay a ransom to
obtain the return of the victim of a kidnaping. An insurance company
may give a reward for the return of an item, “no questions asked.”
And otherwise honest citizens are often willing to buy items that
“fell from a truck” if the price is right. Not
to mention, of course, when municipalities "buy" illegal
guns to get them off the streets.
There
are other situations, equally questionable from a moral point of
view, but which don't seem to be of as great concern to the public –
possibly because most of us can't relate to them,viii
but there are also those which are easily forgiven. If, for example,
someone who gained some money illegally (perhaps by insider trading)
gives that money to a charity desperately in need of funds, should
the charityix,x
and those it serves be penalized by a requirement to repay the
donation? Should an antiquity or piece of art, obtained long before
by unsavory means, that has been on display in a museum for a while –
one obtained by the museum unknowingly and by legal means – be
taken away? How shall we deal with a “legitimate” business, one
providing numerous well-paying jobs, which is owned by a racketeer?
And there are
questions for which, despite legislation, we have no satisfactory
answers. At what point should a clergyman, a lawyer, a doctor, or a
journalist have to reveal information relating to a crime? Should
the criminal benefit from confidentiality? How shall we deal with
“crimes” like prostitution, adultery, overcharging, the copying
of products, and similar ones in which people benefit what many view
as immoral acts?
These
are some of the situations in which a crimexi
occurs and someone benefits. Where do we draw the line? No one has
a problem with the folk song, but the prohibition of using illegally
obtained intelligence is well established in law.xii
Many would argue that somewhere in between, along the “slippery
slope” that separates them, though, that line must exist.
Unfortunately they would all put it in different places. Shall we be
absolutists like the ACLU, or practical people who do “what seems
right at the time?” Where does intent fit in? Does it matter
whether it's the criminal or someone else who benefits? Does it
matter who that “someone else” is? And who decides where the
line is and what's right and what's wrong?
Not all questions
have answers. And not all answers are correct. I'm not an
absolutist. I think there's a line, even if my location may differ
from yours. I can live with that. Justice Potter Stewart said of
pornography, “I can’t define it, but I know it when I see it.”
It's not a very precise answer to the question, but it may be all we
have in some circumstances.
As with beautiful
music, we play some things by ear.
Next
episode: “Morning
Is Dawning”
– What time does class start?
i Yes,
I know it's “breast,” but this seemed more appropriate since it
extends well beyond music. We wrestle with the beast of conflicting
values every day. And that's the real subject of today's essay.
iii The
same is true of music that is not “classical,” although it may
be similarly be based on formal rules. “Popular” music may be
derivative of classical themes, and a jazz performance may include
bits and pieces of many melodies.
iv My
grandson told me that “Maoz
Tsur,” a Hanukkah song,
fit perfectly to the music of “Edelweiss.” He was right, but
because it was protected by copyright, we couldn't do much with his
insight.
v Actually, the use of Nazi information, however inexcusably obtained, may be more justified ethically. It can be argued that although the information was obtained during a horrible sadistic exercise, the goal in some instances was to gain knowledge, even if the science was bad. In the case of the murder, however, there was no “worthy” goal. I doubt, though, that someone who needs a heart would quibble.
vi The
“ticking bomb,” who has information about a terrorist plot or
the planned murder of many, is only one example of this phenomenon.
But it raises the questions of torture and crime prevention. Can we
benefit from the crime of torture, or is it proscribed irrespective
of the justification offered? Must we let people die and then
prosecute the murderer?
viii Like industrial espionage leading to the introduction of new products, competition, and lower prices for the consumer.
x Contributions
may be given as well to political parties or candidates, and they
may be accepted in good faith.
No comments:
Post a Comment
I know you agree, but you can leave comments anyway.