Aeschylus
bound him,i
but Shelleyii
cut him loose. In both cases they were alluding to physical binding
and to the “crime” of bringing fire to mankind. Fire can be both
an important aid to humanity, and a terrible danger. Fire is a
two-edged sword – like so many of our treasures. The forest fire
so feared by everyone can clear away the old dead brush and trees,
leaving room for new growth. But there is much room for disagreement
about fire's value and its risks, as well as about the way it was
obtained. So, although Prometheus thought that stealing fire and
bringing it to humanity was worth the risk, both binding and setting
loose are understandable payments for Prometheus's enterprise.
But
binding is not always a physical act. Less visible, while possibly
more hindering, are the bounds set by society – those that limit
what one can think or say or do. In the wild state, there are no
external bounds set on what an animal does except, perhaps, fear of
the consequences of our actions. An animal may set the boundaries of
the territory that he will defend. The “State of Nature” is
outside of society.iii
There is anarchy, and survival depends upon brains and brawn.
Morality is not an issue.
Within
a society, however, risk is largely mitigated at the cost of some of
the freedom of action that exists outside; survival, stability, and
security increase as anarchy is eliminated. There is law – not the
“law of the jungle,” but man-made statutes for which we are all
accountable. We are bound by the words of the law and of precedents,
even if we had no say in their establishment. A government has been
established to supervise and protect the lives and property of those
in its jurisdiction.
But
who set up that government? And what if we disagree with some of the
rules they established? To what degree do those who preceded us
speak for us? Whatever happened to Democracy?
Unfortunately
we cannot relive the past. We have to live by it. Or maybe it's
“fortunately.” Societyiv
was instituted to protect us from each other, and to set the rules by
which we live. We need laws to guide our actions. Those laws may
have been made by those who preceded us and who, in that sense, speak
for us. At least they speak for us as long as the laws last. It is
a basic tenet of democracy that although we are bound by the
decisions of the past, they are changeable – either by a
modification in the understanding of what those decisions mean, or by
absolute change in the law arrived at through an orderly, democratic,
process.
And
we always have. We accept the constraints of international law (to
some degree, at least), and of parental control and responsibility
for infants, and of proxies in a variety of situations. From time to
time the rules may have to change, but that is in our power.
Our founding document, the Constitution, contains mechanisms for change and, within a year of its adoption, the process of amendment had already begun. The criteria for constitutional change, either by further amendment or by convention, are stiff – perhaps too stiff – but the Founding Fathers established the rules of the game and the states accepted them. And we're bound by them.
Our founding document, the Constitution, contains mechanisms for change and, within a year of its adoption, the process of amendment had already begun. The criteria for constitutional change, either by further amendment or by convention, are stiff – perhaps too stiff – but the Founding Fathers established the rules of the game and the states accepted them. And we're bound by them.
That's
the way rules work. It's the same if they are the rules of a game,
an organization, or a government. For better or worse, it's also a
pattern of human behavior and that may be the reason we accept it so
willingly. We feel ourselves bound by the oaths we take, the
promises we make, and by appointments.v
“That's the way we've always done it” seems to be justification
enough for a rule. It's comfortable. Any deviation from what we've
always done requires good justification. In the interim we yield to
the ones who made the rules.
That's
the weakness of the system though. We defer to the judgments of menvi
who may not be smarter than we but, whether we like it or not, they
got there first, and it's sometimes harder to change the rules than
to set them. It doesn't matter if the rules or laws are just or
unjust. It's easiervii
to go along than to risk punishment for deviation. The deviation may
be from the words of men in the past, or those who have power at
present and can change the rules to suit their own purposes.
Certainly there are those who willingly accept the penalties
resulting from violation of the rules, but they are the minority.viii
Too many of us take a safer path, even if we consider it wrong. We
fear the consequences. It is that kind of fear upon which any
tyrannicalix
government is based.
Also
troubling is the knowledge that whatever the origin of the rules,x
the interpretation of a few individuals – their determination of
what the canons mean – is controlling, whether that was or was not
the intent of those who framed them. We've accepted that also. In
the case of our Constitution and its interpretation, for example, the
Supreme Court can't be questioned,
although constitutional amendment is possible and later on the Court
may change its mind. And in the case of most of our laws, regulators
make the rules by which we have to live. It's not always the
decisions of the past that rule us but often current rule-makers.
But
that's the system. And it doesn't apply to secular laws alone. The
Bible, or Koran, or other foundational document, containing what
believers accept as G-d's word, directs us to the path we must
follow. (We live by the sweat of our brows, and we give birth in
pain because our ancestors strayed from that path. We're bound by
actions as well as words. History tells us that.) The explication
of the details, however, is often decided by humans and we may thus
be obliged to follow man-made, or man-“explained,” rules while we
are trying to comply with divine ordinances. For those who attribute
some or all of what is written in those books to their ancestors, the
mediation of other men, as is the case with the Constitution and the
Founding Fathers, takes the process one step further from the intent
of the author or authors. And since human viewpoints change from
time to time,xi
the understanding of laws – secular or divine – is likely to
change as well.
Is
that the kind of system we want? Do we want to be obliged to follow
rules in whose making we played no part, and with which we may not
agree? It's a hard question to answer, and one with many parts.
From my perspective, however, the bottom line answer is “yes,”
but there are many exceptions, and it's probable that the exceptions
will be different depending on where you live and what the rules are
there. And it will depend on you – what are your core beliefs,
whether you are an absolutist or relativist, and whether you are a
martyr or not.
What
approaches can you take? If you prefer the outlook of another
society to your own, you should consider a change of location. If it
is the religious beliefs with which you take issue, perhaps a change
of religion or its abandonment is worth your consideration. But if
you consider that the rules that you follow are, whatever their
faults, basically appropriate, then you should be working to change
them to the degree that you find them incorrect. It may require
personal sacrifice of time or money or, if you feel strongly enough
about the subject, civil disobedience and the penalties that follow.
But if you believe, as I do, that society, on the whole, is an
improvement on the chaos of the State of Nature, then you'll probably
accept the idea that we are bound by the rules that have been set up,
and they should be followed until we can change them. Laws are a
two-edged sword. They can help us and they can hurt us. But until
we can achieve a society in which they're all good, we'll have to
accept the value and risks they bring.
Next
episode: “Stout Zombies" -- High, not wide.
i “Prometheus
Bound,” Aeschylus (at least it's usually attributed to him),
probably the fifth century BCE.
ii “Prometheus
Unbound,” Percy Bysshe Shelley, 1820.
iii Nature
may still set geographical and meteorological bounds, but the rules
of human interaction are up to us.
iv Which
is, according to Wikipedia, “the
civil power which exists to enforce contracts and the laws of nature
generally.”
v At
least we should.
vi Shorthand
for “people.”
vii And
it requires far less thought. It's easier to do as you're told and
defend your actions with the standard excuse: “I was only
following orders.” It's not always right, however. In fact, it's
usually wrong.
viii Civil
disobedience has a long and honored history. The example of Rosa
Parks is one we should all remember.
ix Whether
fascist, communist, or one based on any other self-serving or
undemocratic practice. When the governing power uses force freely
to control those whom it rules, there will be few who protest. Most
will accept the dictates of those in power rather than risk whatever
consequences follow on their disobedience to the wishes of their
rulers.
x Some
rules are made solely for the benefit of the lawmaker and his
friends.
xi And
from society to society. We call that “cultural relativism.”
No comments:
Post a Comment
I know you agree, but you can leave comments anyway.